The Mystery of Moral Decision-Making 1
Copyright © 1991, by Bill Becker
The mystery of moral decision-making. What are we talking about here?
We all pretty much understand
what it means to make a decision, even without knowing anything about
the particular decision in question.
If someone says, "So, I decided to do it," we know that "it" was one of
several possible things that were
open to the speaker "to do."
"Moral" is a lot tougher, though. It's not clear what the term refers to,
even though it is in constant
use. If our speaker then says "Moreover, I really feel good about doing
the right thing," only the
naive will applaud as if there is universal agreement about "right things."
Most of us will want to
know what the "thing" was before passing judgement on its "rightness" or
"wrongness."
Then we have "moral decision-making," which surely is a different
animal than the "right thing" that
was "done." Moral decision-making is a process, or an activity, that by
definition results in
doing "right" or "wrong" things It involves assessing the consequences
of an action; of weighing the
relative values of pleasure and pain that will result from it; of taking
others' desires and goals
into consideration as well as one's own desires and goals.
This is not to say that moral decision-making implies that any particular
value should be placed on the
desires and goals of others. Indeed, the current destruction of the world's
rainforests follows just
such a consideration of the goals and desires of the indigenous people
who live in them. Here the
decision is that their goals and desires are insignificant compared to
those of the managers of the
cattle and agricultural interests who profit by cutting down the trees. On
the other hand, moral
decision-making does often lead to major changes in our assumptions
about the world and about
others—thus it can be painful in ways that "engineering
decision-making," let's say, usually is not.
"Mystery." The unknown; perhaps the unknowable. Challenging.
Titillating if not too scary. A source
of spiritual growth? Some think so.
A few months ago, I read the book Our Chosen Faith,
co-authored by UU ministers John Buehrens and F.
Forrester Church. They quote the first source of our Unitarian
Universalist religious inspiration:
"direct experience with that transcending mystery and wonder, affirmed in
all cultures, which moves us to
a renewal of the spirit and an openness to the forces that create and
uphold life."
|
So, here we have mystery not only as Angela Lansbury cracking a murder
case that has the professionals
scratching their heads, but also as a source of our deepest hunger for
spiritual wholeness. "Mystery"
is indeed a wonderful term to have such wide and varied referents.
My own taste in mysteries boils down to three, one of which is the
subject of my talk this morning.
Specifically, it is the mystery of how we come to change our own moral
attitudes and behavior. And,
I am confident that most of us have had direct personal experience with
this mystery. I would be
very surprised if almost everyone does not hold definite views about one
moral issue or another, and
has not discussed it vigorously with someone of an opposite
persuasion. I would be incredulous if
any of us has not, more than once, walked away from such a
discussion deeply puzzled at "what it
would take" to get the other person to realize that he or she was
mistaken. The current national
debate on a woman's right to choose an abortion is the perfect
environment for testing my hypothesis.
The behavior that falls under the moral aegis is truly vast, meaning that
our daily experience is rich
in opportunities for fruitful discussion of our moral foundations. And, as
it happens, that is
precisely where my interest as a lay philosopher of ethics lies. In my
approach to human reality I am
much more akin to the particle physicist than to such psychological
"cosmologists" as Freud, Jung,
and the late Joseph Campbell. By this, I mean that I consider
society's condition at any given
moment to be the vector sum of all our preceding values, goals,
decisions, and actions rather than
that society's condition, or repressed racial memories force each
of us into a particular mold.
And I am in good company. Years ago, I found the perfect
metaphor:
... the largest cosmic phenomena we observe are direct functions of the
happenings and internal
workings of the atom. Thus the basic structures of the universe are
governed not so much by the
blazing heat of suns, but by the invisible, unnoticed radiations which
emanate from the individual
atoms deep within each sun. (Science News, circa 1978-79)
|
A similar point-of-view, but specifically referring to us humans, comes from the
great American
philosopher William James:
I am done with great things and big things; with great institutions and big
success, and I am for those
tiny invisible moral forces that work from individual to individual,
creeping through the crannies of
the world like so many rootlets, or the capillary oozing of water, yet if you
give them time, will rend
the hardest monuments of man's pride.
|
Thus, I focus on the individual—on his or her attitude toward the world and
toward others; on his or her
basic values and goals; on what he or she does to achieve those goals; and most
interesting of all, on how
he or she talks about and justifies those goals and actions. Let me give you
some examples of what I mean.
Early this year, at the PSWD conference in Phoenix, I and another
delegate, whom I will call Jane, were
discussing the sorry state of the world. 2 I suggested
that the world
is as it is because no one ever
does anything they believe to be wrong. Jane instantly and emphatically
disagreed with me, leading to
the following conversation:
"Well," I replied, "you don't do anything you believe to be wrong, do you,
Jane?"
"Of course I do," she said.
"But, if I were to ask you why you do such things, you would give me reasons, wouldn't
you?"
"Yes," she said, "but they wouldn't be good reasons—they would be
rationalizations."
"Ok," I said, "let's assume that we have identified an action of yours that you say was wrong, and
that I then ask you
'Jane, why did you do it?' You then search for reasons why you did it, but because you are being
ruthlessly honest
with yourself here, you do not present any of these reasons to me, since each is a
"rationalization." Finally,
after considering them all, you are left with the only one that seems to be acceptable: 'I couldn't
help myself,'
you might say. Or, if you really want to be hard on yourself: 'I did it because I am
weak.'"
"But Jane," I said, "I am being ruthlessly honest here, too, so I say simply: 'Rubbish. You know
perfectly well
that you could have done otherwise.'"
As a Unitarian Universalist (UU), believing in free will and personal responsibility, Jane
had to admit that
I was right.
"Furthermore," I said, "your earlier statement that what you did was wrong itself obscures a
universally recognized,
but less palatable truth—namely that you don't really care as much about the
consequences of your action as you say
you do."
What could Jane say here? Nothing, of course. I then closed the circle.
"Now, Jane," I said, "what would you say if I told you that you should care more than you
do?"
"I'd tell you to stuff it," she shot back without an instant's hesitation.
|
So there you have it. 3 Besides verifying the fact
that none of us want others to instruct us as to our
moral obligations, this exchange with Jane confirmed another conclusion
that I reached years ago:
namely that we can't rely on what others say in our expectations of what
they are likely to do in the
moral arena. Jane's example was a structural one—any "wrong
thing" would have fit the equation.
The situation is not necessarily clearer even when we speak about a
specific moral issue:
Years ago, during a lunch-time discussion typical of the survey party I worked with,
Ralph Nader's name came up.
The party chief, whom I will call Tom, perked up. "Yeah," he said, "take Ralph Nader.
Now there's a guy.
If everybody in the country gave Ralph Nader a dollar a year, that guy could really do
some good." We then
continued to reinforce our common perception that corporate America did not really
have our best interests at
heart.
A week later, I received in the mail an invitation to join Ralph Nader's brand-new
advocacy organization,
Public Citizen. "Wow!" I thought, "Tom is really going to be interested in this."
So, the next day I brought
the application to work. "Hey, Tom," I said, "remember our conversation about
Ralph Nader, and how you said
that if everyone gave him a dollar a year, he could really do some good. Well,
here's your chance. Now, I
know that the membership fee of $15 a year is more than a dollar, but you're
making good money, your house
payments are low, and your daughter just recently moved out, so you can handle
it. How about it, Tom," I
said, "let's both join together."
Well, Tom did not greet this announcement with the enthusiasm one might expect
from his earlier comment about
Ralph Nader's importance to the country's well-being. Indeed, as I talked, he
grew more and more fidgety.
He was clearly looking for a way out, and after a moment or two, I stopped
tormenting him and he kind of
sidled away. I confess that I knew that this would be Tom's response, so I was
more amused than
disappointed.
So here we have two examples that reveal something important about our
attitudes toward moral discourse and
moral obligation, and about what others can expect from us on the basis of what
we say. And, while they were
on the fun side for a serious moral philosopher like me, I have less humorous
examples, also.
Recently, I was present at a conversation in which two of my fellow church
members were discussing democracy
around the world, and "Sam" said that if democracy took hold in the Third World,
our standard of living
would suffer. Sam didn't want that, and was honest enough to accept the only
logical conclusion: from his
viewpoint, democracy for everyone in the world was not necessarily desirable.
When the other UU pointed
out to him that this was directly contrary to our Sunday morning affirmation of
respect for the dignity and
rights of all people, he said simply: "Well, I don't necessarily believe everything
I say on
Sunday morning." 4
Also not much fun was an experience I had with two conservative friends just
after returning from my second
trip to Nicaragua as an election observer in November 1984. I had been
haranguing Jack and Jill since
1980 about the evils of U.S. foreign policy in Central America, with an emphasis
on Nicaragua. My
discourses were a combination of letting off steam and presenting of information.
Their understanding of
the situation in Nicaragua was derived from a reliance on the mainstream media
and hearsay. They had never
expressed rock-solid support for Reagan's policy, and I had no reason to believe
that such was their
position.
Throughout my polemics, Jill was a saint—she listened patiently,
and even though she could not bring
herself to condemn the so-called low-intensity war outright, I could see
that she was touched by my
stories of atrocities committed against Nicaraguan peasants by President
Reagan's "freedom fighters."
I also discussed the positive achievements of the Sandinistas—their
offers to negotiate non-aggression
pacts with their neighbors, and other well-documented evidence that they
were not such a threat to
Harlingen, Texas as Reagan made them out to be. I made sure to
mention my sources regularly: the
National Catholic Reporter, the New York Times, the Los Angeles
Times, the Christian Science Monitor,
L.A. Weekly, as well as Amnesty International, Americas Watch, and the
National Congress on Latin
America. Over time, I could see that Jill had serious doubts as to whether
the benefits of this war
outweighed the pain suffered by the Nicaraguans.
During these sessions, though, Jack remained in the background puttering
with one thing or another. He
never said a word, except occasionally to joke about my "pinko"
proclivities. On this occasion, I
commented that Reagan's invasion of Grenada was a test—would a
majority of the American people also
support an invasion of Nicaragua? For the first time, Jack spoke on the
subject: "Well, I certainly
hope so," he said.
The room went ice cold, and after a few uncomfortable moments the
conversation picked up on another
subject. Later, I asked Jack if he understood what an invasion of
Nicaragua would mean—did he realize
how much killing and destruction would result? I said that he had heard
my stories, and that he knew
that I was not trying to con him—that while I might be mistaken
about a particular here and there, the
overwhelming body of evidence supported my contention that we were
engaged in a profoundly immoral and
totally unnecessary war against Nicaragua. Jack didn't even try to deny
the basic accuracy of my
information, or to impugn my motives or the integrity of my sources. "I
know you've studied the issue
much more than I have," he said, "but I know how I feel."
What is important here, of course, is not that Jack disagreed with me.
What I found chilling was his
willingness to see a bloodbath in Nicaragua without ever seriously
questioning the reasons for it.
Let me move now from personal anecdotes, which I hope have reminded
you of similar instances in your own
lives, to the debunking of a mystery or two.
I have often heard people remark about how difficult it is to make a
decision about an important moral
issue, usually because of an abundance of clearly partisan sources of
information. I call this
particular syndrome "the inclination to helpless confusion." It is
recognizable through two major
symptoms: one is a kind of hand-wringing lament—how can one
decide if one doesn't know who is telling
the truth? If only we could be sure of knowing all the facts, then we
could make the right decision.
The other is a fallback to cynicism: since no one is clearly lying, all are
assumed to be dishonest.
Besides, haven't philosophers shown that the notion of "truth" is
itself an illusion.
Years ago, I encountered a perfect example of how the inclination to
helpless confusion is used by
sophisticated players with an interest in creating mystery where there is
none. Around the time the
CIA distributed a manual advocating the selective assassination of
Nicaraguans sympathetic to the
Sandinista government, former Arizona Senator Barry Goldwater spoke
to the Arizona Chamber of
Commerce Business Roundtable. He was discussing the possible role of
U.S. combat troops in Central
America, at the height of the protest movement against U.S.
intervention there. After saying that he
would not send troops to any other region of the world except
Central America "which is just 800
miles south of us," Goldwater comments "It's a very mixed up,
muddled picture there, and we don't
know who wears the white hats or the black hats."
In fact, there could be no mystery at all here as to who Goldwater thought
wore the white hats and who
wore the black hats. He was then Chairman of the Senate Intelligence
Committee, which among other
responsibilities is charged with oversight of the CIA. He was one of the
nation's preeminent hawks,
and had historically approved all U.S. efforts to prevent the
smallest germ of socialism from
taking hold in this hemisphere. Thus, to imply that he had no
opinion as to whether the contras,
for example, or the leftist Sandinistas deserved U.S. military aid
was a transparent attempt to
deceive his audience. (Sadly, I have lost or misplaced the
reference for this incident.)
There is no mention of whether any Roundtable member questioned
Goldwater's competence as chair of
the intelligence committee, but it is a safe bet that no one did. I can
easily imagine them
looking at each other helplessly, as if to say, "If good ol' Barry can't
figure out what's happening
down there, how can we?" Thus might they prepare themselves for their
own attempts to mystify the
issue for others.
This helpless confusion also arises in discussions of how we might create
a fairer society, with more
opportunity for everyone. And, it really does seem to be a mystery. In
fact, the task is so large
that it is often easier to deny that there is a problem than to even think
about a solution.
But is there really any mystery about how the world can be made a better
place for all? None whatever.
In fact, the basis of personal action toward a better world is beautifully
elegant: The way to create
a just society, or a just world, for that matter, is for none of us to
strive for more than we need to
be reasonably comfortable until everyone has access to the
fundamental necessities for a
dignified life. 5
Some might say that I am oversimplifying here. That's what they said to
Einstein and Copernicus, too.
Moreover, I suggest that most of us understand this perfectly well;
some, like Mother Theresa, and
Albert Schweitzer carry the idea to its logical conclusion, and
dedicate their lives to living and
working with the poor. Certainly this notion is consistent with
Buddha's refusal to enter paradise
until everyone had achieved his level of enlightenment.
That we understand this simple truth is shown by a typical response to
such examples of high moral
purpose and action as Mother Theresa and Schweitzer. First there is a
statement of admiration for
their love and concern for others, followed quickly by another statement
to the effect that we can't
all be like them. The important thing here is that this second statement
is something of a fib.
Anyone who would understand the moral import of Mother Theresa's
and Schweitzer's lives undoubtedly
insists upon their own freedom to choose how to live. Thus they
know that they could choose as these
two chose. They also know that even if one chooses not to live at
such an austere level, one could
still choose to live more simply, thus freeing resources and dollars
for a "more equitable
distribution of wealth" as our liberal but decidedly amateur
economists put it.
And, in fact, we have here another aspect of the mystery to ponder.
Among the population that might
express admiration for such humanitarians as Mother Theresa, we can
expect to find a smaller number
who routinely promote, or tacitly accept, violence as the means to the
lofty goals they say they
admire. Here I have in mind the average CIA covert action specialist, as
well as some highly
respected—even venerated—"sages" in the field of U.S.
foreign policy.
So far, then, we have seen that knowledge of the facts is not necessarily
effective in promoting a
change in one's moral foundations.
There are other means whereby a change of heart might come about.
Sometimes—usually not by choice—we
actually live the old saw about walking in the other person's moccasins.
We then might come to
understand the world as the other does, which probably does increase the
chance that we will take the
other more into consideration if and when we return to our own lives.
This was exactly the
experience of Reverend Benjamin Weir, who was kidnaped by
pro-Iranian militants in Lebanon.
After his release in September, 1985, he said: "My captivity has led me
to a deepened sympathy for
people who are incarcerated, especially for causes over which they
have no control, and for those
who by illness or circumstances of life are in some way
imprisoned or confined, lonely, and in
distress." (Reference lost)
We can assume that as a minister, Weir was already a leg up in the
concern-for-the-prisoner department.
Thus, his sentiment is an important endorsement of putting oneself in
the other's place.
It is also likely that we sometimes change our attitudes and behavior only
when it becomes fashionable
to do so. In the early days of the environmental movement, there was
much ridicule of those who were
so concerned about Bambi that they would deprive me of the rich wood
paneling that I had chosen for my
den. Now enough people have gotten onto the environmental bandwagon
that even the corporate types are
expressing a commitment to the planet's preservation. A while back the
headline in the newsletter of
the Arrowhead Drinking Water company read "Recycling: the new
morality." As pleased as I was to
read it, I nonetheless wondered whether Arrowhead's management had
long promoted recycling as a
moral good, or whether the headline was just an example of
getting on a popular bandwagon.
It is also the case that we are more likely to pay attention to a moral
message when the messenger, or,
let's say, the victim, looks and talks like us. Michael Zinzun is a large
black man who wears a snood
over his plentiful "afro" styled hair. He lost an eye at the hands of the
Pasadena police department
several years ago, and has worked hard trying to get an elected civilian
police review board established
for the City of Los Angeles. He is the last person that the average middle
class white would want to
see on such a board, even though he seems as qualified as the political
types who were appointed to the
board that was established in response to the beating of black motorist
Rodney King by the Los Angeles
police officers.
In this same line, last winter Congress passed a law restricting military
aid to the government of
Guatemala to protest its excessive reliance on force to remain in power.
But the Guatemalan
military has been killing peasants for years, and Congress went along
with Bush's reinstatement of
military aid soon after he took office. Why so late with the punitive
cut-off? Very simple:
the military killed an American (allegedly by accident).
It also happens quite often that we change our ideas about what is right or
wrong when we change our
goals, and these new goals are founded on a different set of moral
principles than we had earlier
subscribed to. After a period of youthful and idealistic protest against
U.S. foreign policy and the
Vietnam War, more than a few student protesters decided to make a
living. Some of them decided that
their best shot at the good life was to take a job in the defense industry.
Now they believe that the
arms race was a necessary evil.
CONCLUSION
As I said at the beginning of this talk, I didn't expect us to solve the
mystery of moral
decision-making this morning, and I don't think we have even
come close. I have not heard from
anyone, anywhere, anything even resembling the solution. Often,
we are offered answers that are not
answers at all. Here, "human nature" might well be used to
"explain" my friend Tom's reluctance to
support Ralph Nader, or my friend Jack's hope for a war against
Nicaragua. Perhaps Freud can be
brought in, and the UU who didn't believe everything he said on
Sunday morning can be understood in
terms of the Id, the Ego, and the Super-ego.
None of these abstractions are answers, and I consider most of them to be
useless as conceptual
frameworks for dealing with the riddle of human behavior. Do rich
people give a lower percentage of
their disposable income to charity than do the poor because they were
improperly potty-trained?
Did Ivan Boesky and Charles Keating steal millions because they missed
a rung on Maslow's heirarchy of
needs? To all such suggestions, I say "Rubbish!"
I do not see any real mystery in the world I have spoken of this morning.
The problems we face are
obvious. The solutions are obvious. The mystery of what triggers that
particular moral transformation
that will inspire us to implement the solutions lies within each of us.
But even here there is no
mystery as to the strictly honest approach to our
being-in-the-world: it is to admit straight out
that we are not helpless, and then do something. If we are
confused, the answer is to get as much
information as we can. After a while, a conclusion will settle in.
Then we can devise a plan of
action—even if it is a modest one. That is enough for now.
POSTSCRIPT
The day before delivering this talk, I drove to San Diego County,
far enough south to pass the
Immigration and Naturalization Service inspection station. For
several miles on either side of the
station, spaced regularly on the side of the roadway, the motorist
sees yellow diamond-shaped
warning signs. The signs are large, accommodating text and a
sizeable graphic image. The text
reads "Warning: people crossing the road." The graphic is a
silhouette of three people: a man
leads a woman by the hand, who in turn is leading a small girl by
the hand in a run across the
freeway's five lanes of traffic. The flying dresses of the woman
and the girl almost convince
the motorist that the three silhouettes are about to leap off the sign
and onto the freeway in a
real run for their lives. And, as if these signs aren't enough, huge
banners span the
entire roadway width close on either side of the station. No
graphic, but virtually the same
message; "Watch for people crossing the road."
After imagining the fear the illegal aliens must feel as they make a dash
in the hope of avoiding the
INS, I thought of the increasing levels of poverty we are seeing here in
the United States. This in
turn reminded me of the growing gap between the rich and the poor, and
my fear that sooner or later the
rich will decide that they need official protection from the rest of us.
Such a thought might
already have occurred to some of our wealthier and more politically
imaginative citizens, and I see
no difficulty for them in using their influence with politicians and the
press to turn a militant
demonstration by poor people, let's say, into an amorphous but
vividly imagined threat to the safety
of an increasingly skittish middle class. Thus might the nation's
police forces become the
protectors of the nation against the now "more numerous but less
easily defined terrorist
threats" evoked by former CIA director William Webster in his
response to the demise of the "Soviet
threat." Thus might America become an overtly fascist nation.
But that doesn't mean things would necessarily be all bad. Along the
same stretch of freeway I noticed
the modest signs that are becoming common now as corporations and
even individuals respond to President
Bush's call for a "thousand points of light." The signs herald the
generosity of those who "adopt a
highway," and (presumably) pay for the cleanup of litter along a
particular stretch of the road.
Whether Lion's Club or Kiwanis members, for example, or singer
and film star Bette Middler are
acting from offended aesthetic sensibilities, or have decided to
humor motorists who want clean
freeways but don't want to pay for them is not clear, but there the
signs are, testifying to their
civic virtue.
And it is easy to imagine such a generous spirit catching hold in the
realm of the obscenely rich as
well. Paying a few poor people out of a vast pool of funds to do the work
that can no longer be done
through the public sector would provide them with a few dollars, and
undoubtedly a tax write-off for
the benefactor as well. There might even be an advantage in organizing
"thousand points of light"
task forces to be used for whatever public benefit the
philanthropists decided to provide. These
wealthy could be imbued with an aura of almost god-like
beneficence by skilled public relations
specialists, thus making it an honor to work for the labor
contractor who gathers the strong arms
and backs for the project of the hour.
It may be that the well-off give less to charity than their poor compatriots,
relatively speaking, just
because they are "merely" well off. Thus, in the coming period, as more
of the nation's money supply
flows to fewer individuals, their sense of security and surfeit might
become so strong that the
satisfaction of providing all the services historically reserved to
government could relegate the
impulse to wealth per se to a level or two below a congenial self-image
of compassionate and
caring Americans. Thus might the historic image of the robber baron,
and the modern image of
the Enron manager, also be erased from the public memory.
But, there would always be some churlish enough not to enjoy such a
pleasant feudalism, and who might
then try to convince those who seem outwardly happy with their station
in life that they should not be
so happy after all. This danger could always be nipped in whatever bud
it appears by a comprehensive
network of domestic spies and tried-and-true methods of intimidation.
Ideally, society would finally
settle down to a steady state in which there would be no serious
threat to those who control money,
land and resources. Who could challenge them? Why would
anyone want to? Wouldn't the rich
finally be doing everything dear to the liberal and to the bleeding
heart?
What more could anyone ask?
Bill Becker, West Hills, CA 18Dec91
Endnotes:
- Adaptation of a talk presented at the Unitarian Universalist Fellowship of Laguna Beach,
December 15, 1991.
Slightly revised, February, 1994; May 2004.
- "Jane" is a pseudonym for the other participant here (who is a woman, however). She
graciously gave me
permission to use her real name in the original talk I gave at various Unitarian Universalist
churches, because it
was all "in the family," so to speak. Since this revision is intended to travel farther afield,
however, I have
decided on anonymity for her.
- Jane and I parted friends, of course, and she felt challenged enough to invite me to speak
at her church. The
talk I gave there was titled "Why we live in the best of all possible worlds."
- The conversation with did have an effect, though. After re-thinking his statements, Sam
softened, and is now more
sensitive to the aspirations of third world people, and less inclined to dismiss them as incapable
of understanding
democracy.
- I was very pleased to find an affirmation of my thought here from an unexpected quarter.
"The Environment's
New Clothes," reports the new "green" approach now gaining momentum in the garment
industry. As well as mentioning
the "environmental audits" of fabric suppliers now being conducted regularly by their clothing
maker clients, the
article details the major fabric types and lists the environmental pluses and minuses of each.
Finally, though,
after noting that no fabric product is totally environmentally compatible, the report ends with
a comment from a
textile expert: "Buy fewer clothes, that's the ultimate." Christian Science
Monitor, August 19, 1993
|